6 – Specific Counterproductivity
Iatrogenesis will be controlled only if it is understood as but one
aspect of the destructive dominance of industry over society, as but
one instance of that paradoxical counterproductivity which is now
surfacing in all major industrial sectors. Like time-consuming
acceleration, stupefying education, self-destructive military defense,
disorienting information, or unsettling housing projects, pathogenic
medicine is the result of industrial overproduction that paralyzes
autonomous action. In order to focus on this specific
counterproductivity of contemporary industry, frustrating
overproduction must be clearly distinguished from two other categories
of economic burdens with which it is generally confused, namely,
declining marginal utility and negative externality. Without this
distinction of the specific frustration that constitutes
counterproductivity from rising prices and oppressive social costs, the
social assessment of any technical enterprise, be it medicine,
transportation, the media, or education, will remain limited to an
accounting of cost-efficiency and not even approach a radical critique
of the instrumental effectiveness of these various sectors.
Direct costs reflect rental charges, payments made for labor,
materials, and other considerations. The production cost of a
passenger-mile includes the payments made to build and operate the
vehicle and the road, as well as the profit that accrues to those who
have obtained control over transportation: the interest charged by the
capitalists who own the tools of production, and the perquisites
claimed by the bureaucrats who monopolize the stock of knowledge that
is applied in the process. The price is the sum of these various
rentals, no matter whether it is paid by the consumer out of his own
pocket or by a tax-supported social agency that purchases on his behalf.
Negative externality is the name of the social costs that are not
included in the monetary price; it is the common designation for the
burdens, privations, nuisances, and injuries that I impose on others by
each passenger-mile I travel. The dirt, the noise, and the ugliness my
car adds to the city; the harm caused by collisions and pollution; the
degradation of the total environment by the oxygen I burn and the
poisons I scatter; the increasing costliness of the police department;
and also the traffic-related discrimination against the poor: all are
negative externalities associated with each passenger-mile. Some can
easily be internalized in the purchase price, as for instance the
damages done by collisions, which are paid for by insurance. Other
externalities that do not now show up in the market price could be
internalized in the same way: the cost of therapy for cancer caused by
exhaust fumes could be added to each gallon of fuel, to be spent for
cancer detection and surgery or for cancer prevention through
antipollution devices and gas masks. But most externalities cannot be
quantified and internalized: if gasoline prices are raised to reduce
depletion of oil stocks and of atmospheric oxygen, each passenger- mile
becomes more costly and more of a privilege; environmental damage is
lessened but social injustice is increased. Beyond a certain level of
intensity of industrial production, externalities cannot be reduced but
only shifted around.
Counterproductivity is something other than either an individual or a
social cost; it is distinct from the declining utility obtained for a
unit of currency and from all forms of external disservice. It exists
whenever the use of an institution paradoxically takes away from
society those things the institution was designed to provide. It is a
form of built-in social frustration. The price of a commodity or a
service measures what the purchaser is willing to spend for whatever he
gets; externalities indicate what society will tolerate to allow for
this consumption; counterproductivity gauges the degree of prevalent
cognitive dissonance resulting from the transaction: it is a social
indicator for the built-in counterpurposive functioning of an economic
sector. The iatrogenic intensity of our medical enterprise is only a
particularly painful example of how frustrating overproduction appears
in equal measure as time-consuming acceleration of traffic, static in
communications, training for well-rounded incompetence in education,
uprooting as a result of housing development, and destructive
overfeeding. This specific counterproductivity constitutes an unwanted
side-effect of industrial production which cannot be externalized from
the particular economic sector that produces it. Fundamentally it is
due neither to technical mistakes nor to class exploitation but to
industrially generated destruction of those environmental, social, and
psychological conditions needed for the development of nonindustrial or
nonprofessional use- values. Counterproductivity is the result of an
industrially induced paralysis of practical self-governing activity.
The industrial distortion of our shared perception of reality has
rendered us blind to the counterpurposive level of our enterprise. We
live in an epoch in which learning is planned, residence standardized,
traffic motorized, and communication programmed, and in which, for the
first time, a large part of all foodstuffs consumed by humanity passes
through interregional markets. In such an intensely industrialized
society, people are conditioned to get things rather than to do them;
they are trained to value what can be purchased rather than what they
themselves can create. They want to be taught, moved, treated, or
guided rather than to learn, to heal, and to find their own way.
Impersonal institutions are assigned personal functions. Healing ceases
to be considered a task for the sick. It first becomes the duty of the
individual body repairmen, and then soon changes from a personal
service into the output of an anonymous agency. In the process, society
is rearranged for the sake of the health-care system, and it becomes
increasingly difficult to care for one's own health. Goods and services
litter the domains of freedom.
Schools produce education, motor vehicles produce locomotion, and
medicine produces health care. These outputs are staples that have all
the characteristics of commodities. Their production costs can be added
to or subtracted from the GNP, their scarcity can be measured in terms
of marginal value, and their costs can be established in currency
equivalents. By their very nature these staples create a market. Like
school education and motor transportation, clinical care is the result
of a capital-intensive commodity production; the services produced are
designed for others, not with others nor for the producer.
Owing to the industrialization of our world-view, it is often
overlooked that each of these commodities still competes with a
nonmarketable use-value that people freely produce, each on his own.
People learn by seeing and doing, they move on their feet, they heal,
they take care of their health, and they contribute to the health of
others. These activities have use-values that resist marketing. Most
valuable learning, body movement, and healing do not show up on the
GNP. People learn their mother tongue, move around, produce their
children and bring them up, recover the use of broken bones, and
prepare the local diet, and do these things with more or less
competence and enjoyment. These are all valuable activities which most
of the time will not and cannot be undertaken for money, but which can
be devalued if too much money is around.
The achievement of a concrete social goal cannot be measured in terms
of industrial outputs, neither in their amount nor in the curve that
represents their distribution and their social costs. The effectiveness
of each industrial sector is determined by the correlation between the
production of commodities by society and the autonomous production of
corresponding use-values. How effective a society is in producing high
levels of mobility, housing, or nutrition depends on the meshing of
marketed staples with inalienable, spontaneous action.
When most needs of most people are satisfied in a domestic or community
mode of production, the gap between expectation and gratification tends
to be narrow and stable. Learning, locomotion, or sick-care are the
results of highly decentralized initiatives, of autonomous inputs and
self-limiting total outputs. Under the conditions of a subsistence
economy, the tools used in production determine the needs that the
application of these same tools can fulfill. For instance, people know
what they can expect when they get sick. Somebody in the village or the
nearby town will know all the remedies that have worked in the past,
and beyond this lies the unpredictable realm of the miracle. Until late
in the nineteenth century, most families, even in Western countries,
provided most of the therapy that was known. Most learning, locomotion,
or healing was performed by each man on his own, and the tools needed
were produced in his family or village setting.
Autonomous production can, of course, be supplemented by industrial
outputs that will have to be designed and often manufactured beyond
direct community control. Autonomous activity can be rendered both more
effective and more decentralized by using such industrially made tools
as bicycles, printing presses, recorders, or X-ray equipment. But it
can also be hampered, devalued, and blocked by an arrangement of
society that is totally in favor of industry. The synergy between the
autonomous and the heteronomous modes of production then takes on a
negative cast. The arrangement of society in favor of managed commodity
production has two ultimately destructive aspects: people are trained
for consumption rather than for action, and at the same time their
range of action is narrowed. The tool separates the workman from his
labor. Habitual bicycle commuters are pushed off the road by
intolerable levels of traffic, and patients accustomed to taking care
of their own ailments find yesterday's remedies available only on
prescription and hence largely unobtainable. Wage labor and client
relationships expand while autonomous production and gift relationships
wither.
Effectively achieving social objectives depends on the degree to which
the two fundamental modes of production supplement or hamper each
other. Effectively coming to know and to control a given physical and
social environment depends on people's formal education and on their
opportunity and motivation to learn in a nonprogrammed way. Effective
traffic depends on the ability of people to get where they must go
quickly and conveniently. Effective sick-care depends on the degree to
which pain and dysfunction are made tolerable and recovery is enhanced.
The effective satisfaction of these needs must be clearly distinguished
from the efficiency with which industrial products are made and
marketed, from the number of certificates, passenger-miles, housing
units, or medical interventions performed. Beyond a certain threshold,
these outputs will all be needed only as remedies; they will substitute
for personal activities that previous industrial outputs have
paralyzed. The social criteria by which effective need-satisfaction can
be evaluated do not match the measurements used to evaluate the
production and marketing of industrial goods.
Since measurements disregard the contributions made by the autonomous
mode towards the total effectiveness with which any major social goal
may be achieved, they cannot indicate if this total effectiveness is
increasing or decreasing. The number of graduates, for instance, might
be inversely related to general competence. Much less can technical
measurements indicate who are the beneficiaries and who are the losers
from industrial growth, who are the few that get more and can do more,
and who fall into the majority whose marginal access to industrial
products is compounded by their loss of autonomous effectiveness. Only
political judgment can assess the balance.
The persons most hurt by counterproductive institutionalization are
usually not the poorest in monetary terms. The typical victims of the
depersonalization of values are the powerless in a milieu made for the
industrially enriched. Among the powerless may be people who are
relatively affluent within their society or those who are inmates of
benevolent total institutions. Disabling dependence reduces them to
modernized poverty. Policies meant to remedy the new sense of privation
will not only be futile but will aggravate the damage. By promising
more staples rather than protecting autonomy, they will intensify
disabling dependence.
The poor in Bengal or Peru still survive with occasional employment and
an occasional dip into the market economy: they live by the timeless
art of making do. They still can stretch out provisions, alternate
between fat and lean periods, knit gift relationships whereby they
barter or otherwise exchange goods and services neither made for nor
accounted for by the market. In the country, in the absence of
television, they enjoy living in homes built on traditional models.
Drawn or pushed into town, they squat on the margins of the
steel-and-petroleum sector, where they build a provisional economy with
scraps of waste that can serve as building blocks for self-made shacks.
Their exposure to extreme famine grows with their dependence on
marketed food.
Given sufficient generations, during its entire evolution Homo sapiens
has shown high competence in developing a great variety of cultural
forms, each meant to keep the total population of a region within the
limits of resources that could be shared or formally exchanged in its
limited milieu. The worldwide and homogeneous disabling of the communal
coping ability of local populations has developed with imperialism and
its contemporary variants of industrial development and compassionate
chic.
The invasion of the underdeveloped countries by new instruments of
production organized for financial efficiency rather than local
effectiveness and for professional rather than lay control inevitably
disqualifies tradition and autonomous learning and creates the need for
therapy from teachers, doctors, and social workers. While road and
radio mold the lives of those whom they reach to industrial standards,
they degrade their handicrafts, housing, or health care much faster
than they crush the skills they replace. Aztec massage gives relief to
many who would no longer admit it because they believe it outdated. The
common family bed becomes disreputable much faster than its occupants
become aware of discomfort. Where development plans have worked, they
have often succeeded because of the unforeseen resilience of the
adobe-cum-oildrum sector. The continued ability to produce foods on
marginal land and in city backyards has saved productivity campaigns
from the Ukraine to Venezuela. The ability to care for the sick, the
old, and the insane without nurses or wardens has buffered the majority
against the rising specific disutilities which symbolic enrichment has
brought. Poverty in the subsistence sector, even when this subsistence
is retrenched by considerable market dependence, does not crush
autonomy. People remain motivated to squat on thoroughfares, to nibble
at professional monopolies, or to circumvent the bureaucrats.
When perception of personal needs is the result of professional
diagnosis, dependence turns into painful disability. The aged in the
United States can again serve as the paradigm. They have been trained
to experience urgent needs that no level of relative privilege can
possibly satisfy. The more tax money that is spent to bolster their
frailty, the keener is their awareness of decay. At the same time,
their ability to take care of themselves has withered, as social
arrangements allowing them to exercise autonomy have practically
disappeared. The aged are an example of the specialization of poverty
which the over-specialization of services can bring forth. The elderly
in the United States are only one extreme example of suffering promoted
by high-cost deprivation. Having learned to consider old age akin to
disease, they have developed unlimited economic needs in order to pay
for interminable therapies, which are usually ineffective, are
frequently demeaning and painful, and call more often than not for
reclusion in a special milieu.
Five faces of industrially modernized poverty appear caricatured in the
pampered ghettos of rich men's retirement: the incidence of chronic
disease increases as fewer people die in their youth; more people
suffer clinical damage from health measures; medical services grow more
slowly than the spread and urgency of demand; people find fewer
resources in their environment and culture to help them come to terms
with their suffering, and thus are forced to depend on medical services
for a wider range of trivia; people lose the ability to live with
impairment or pain and become dependent on the management of every
discomfort by specialized service personnel. The cumulative result of
overexpansion in the health-care industry has thwarted the power of
people to respond to challenges and to cope with changes in their
bodies or in their environment.
The destructive power of medical overexpansion does not, of course,
mean that sanitation, inoculation, and vector control, well-distributed
health education, healthy architecture, and safe machinery, general
competence in first aid, equally distributed access to dental and
primary medical care, as well as judiciously selected complex services,
could not all fit into a truly modern culture that fostered self-care
and autonomy. As long as engineered intervention in the relationship
between individuals and environment remains below a certain intensity,
relative to the range of the individual's freedom of action, such
intervention could enhance the organism's competence in coping and
creating its own future. But beyond a certain level, the heteronomous
management of life will inevitably first restrict, then cripple, and
finally paralyze the organism's nontrivial responses, and what was
meant to constitute health care will turn into a specific form of
health denial.
7 – Political Countermeasures
Fifteen years ago it would have been impossible to get a hearing for
the claim that medicine itself might be a danger to health. In the
early 1960s, the British National Health Service still enjoyed a
worldwide reputation, particularly among American reformers. The
service, created by Albert Beveridge, was based on the assumption that
there exists in every population a strictly limited amount of morbidity
which, if treated under conditions of equity, will eventually decline.
Thus Beveridge had calculated that the annual cost of the Health
Service would fall as therapy reduced the rate of illness. Health
planners and welfare economists never expected that the service's
redefinition of health would broaden the scope of medical care and that
only budgetary restrictions would keep it from expanding indefinitely.
It was not predicted that soon, in a regional screening, only
sixty-seven out of one thousand people would be found completely fit
and that 50 percent would be referred to a doctor, while according to
another study, one in six people screened would be defined as suffering
from one to nine serious illnesses. Nor had the health planners
forecast that the threshold of tolerance for everyday reality would
decline as fast as the competence for self-care was undermined, and
that one-quarter of all visits to the doctor for free service would be
for the untreatable common cold. Between 1943 and 1951, 75 percent of
the persons questioned claimed to have suffered from illness during the
preceding month. By 1972, 95 percent of those surveyed in one study
considered themselves unwell during the fourteen days prior to
questioning, and in another study in which 5 percent considered
themselves free of symptoms, 9 percent claimed to have suffered from
more than six different symptoms in the two weeks just past. Least of
all did the health planners make provision for the new diseases that
would become endemic through the same process that made medicine at
least partially effective. They did not forecast the need for special
hospitals dedicated to the soothing of terminal pain, usually suffered
by the victims of unsound or ineffective surgery for cancer, or the
need for other hospital beds for those affected by medicine-induced
disease.
The sixties also witnessed the rise and fall of a multinational
consortium for the export of optimism to the third world which took
shape in the Peace Corps, the Alliance for Progress, Israeli aid to
Central Africa, and in the last brush-fires of medical-missionary zeal.
The Western belief that its medicines could cure the ills of the
nonindustrialized tropics was then at its height. International
cooperation had just won major battles against mosquitoes, microbes,
and parasites, ultimately Pyrrhic victories which were advertised as
the beginning of a final solution to tropical disease. The role that
economic and technological development would play in spreading and
aggravating sleeping sickness, bilharziasis, and even malaria was not
yet suspected. Those who saw world hunger and new pestilence on the
horizon were treated like prophets of doom or romantics; the Green
Revolution was still considered the opening phase of a healthier and
more equitable world. It would have seemed unbelievable that within ten
years malnutrition in two forms would become by far the most important
threat to modern man. The new high- caloric undernourishment of poor
populations was not foreseen, nor was the fact that overfeeding would
be identified as the main cause for the epidemic diseases of the rich.
In the United States the new frontiers had not yet been obstructed by
competing bureaucratic schemes. Hopes for better health still focused
on equality of access to the agencies that would do away with specific
diseases, Iatrogenesis was still an issue for the paranoid.
But by 1975 much of this had changed. A generation ago, children in
kindergarten had painted the doctor as a white-coated father-figure.
Today, however, they will just as readily paint him as a man from Mars
or a Frankenstein. Muckracking feeds on medical charts and doctors' tax
returns, and a new mood of wariness among patients has caused medical
and pharmaceutical companies to triple their expenses for public
relations. Ralph Nader has made the consumers of health staples
money-and quality-conscious. The ecological movement has created an
awareness that health depends on the environment—on food and working
conditions and housing — and Americans have come to accept the idea
that they are threatened by pesticides, additives, and mycotoxins and
other health risks due to environmental degradation. Women's liberation
has highlighted the key role that the control over one's body plays in
health care. A few slum communities have assumed responsibility for
basic health care and have tried to unhook their members from
dependence on outsiders. The class-specific nature of body perception,
language, concepts, access to health services, infant mortality, and
actual, specifically chronic, morbidity has been widely documented, and
the class-specific origins and prejudices of physicians are beginning
to be understood. The World Health Organization, meanwhile, is moving
to a conclusion that would have shocked most of its founders: in a
recent publication WHO advocates the deprofessionalization of primary
care as the most important single step in raising national health
levels.
Doctors themselves are beginning to look askance at what doctors do.
When physicians in New England were asked to evaluate the treatment
their patients had received from other doctors, most were dissatisfied.
Depending on the method of peer evaluation used, between 1.4 percent
and 63 percent of patients were believed to have received adequate
care. Patients are told ever more frequently by their doctors that they
have been damaged by previous medication and that the treatment now
prescribed is made necessary by the effects of such prior medication,
which in some cases was given in a life-saving endeavor, but much more
often for weight control, mild hypertension, flu, or mosquito bite or
just to put a mutually satisfactory conclusion to an interview with the
doctor. In 1973 a retiring senior official of the U.S. Department of
Health, Education, and Welfare could say that 80 percent of all funds
channeled through his office provided no demonstrable benefits to
health and that much of the rest was spent to offset iatrogenic damage.
His successor will have to deal with these data if he wants to maintain
public trust.
Patients are starting to listen, and a growing number of movements and
organizations are beginning to demand reform. The attacks are founded
on five major categories of criticism and are directed to five
categories of reform: (1) Production of remedies and services has
become self-serving. Consumer lobbies and consumer control of hospital
boards should therefore force doctors to improve their wares. (2) The
delivery of remedies and access to services is unequal and arbitrary;
it depends either on the patient's money and rank, or on social and
medical prejudices which favor, for example, attention to heart disease
over attention to malnutrition. The nationalization of health
production ought to control the hidden biases of the clinic. (3) The
organization of the medical guild perpetuates inefficiency and
privilege, while professional licensing of specialists fosters an
increasingly narrow and specialized view of disease. A combination of
capitation payment with institutional licensing ought to combine
control over doctors with the interest of patients. (4) The sway of one
kind of medicine deprives society of the benefits competing sects might
offer. More public support for alpha waves, encounter groups, and
chiropractic ought to countervail and complement the scalpel and the
poison. (5) The main thrust of present medicine is the individual, in
sickness or in health. More resources for the engineering of
populations and environments ought to stretch the health dollar.
These proposed remedial policies could control to some degree the
social costs created by overmedicalization. By joining together,
consumers do have power to get more for their money; welfare
bureaucracies do have the power to reduce inequalities; changes in
licensing and in modes of financing can protect the population not only
against nonprofessional quacks but also, in some cases, against
professional abuse; money transferred from the production of human
spare parts to the reduction of industrial risks does buy more "health"
per dollar. But all these policies, unless carefully qualified, will
tend to reduce the externalities created by medicine at the cost of a
further increase of medicine's paradoxical counterproduct, its negative
effect on health. All tend to stimulate further medicalization. All
consistently place the improvement of medical services above those
factors which would improve and equalize opportunities, competence, and
confidence for self- care; they deny the civil liberty to live and to
heal, and substitute promises of more conspicuous social entitlements
to care by a professional.
In the following five sections I will deal with some of these possible countermeasures and examine their relative merits.
Consumer Protection for Addicts
When people become aware of their dependence on the medical industry,
they tend to be trapped in the belief that they are already hopelessly
hooked. They fear a life of disease without a doctor much as they would
feel immobilized without a car or a bus. In this state of mind they are
ready to be organized for consumer protection and to seek solace from
politicians who will check the high-handedness of medical producers.40
The need for such self-protection is obvious, the implicit dangers
obscure. The sad truth for consumer advocates is that neither control
of cost nor assurance of quality guarantees that health will be served
by medicine that measures up to present medical standards.
Consumers who band together to force General Motors to produce an
acceptable car have begun to feel competent to look under the hood and
to develop criteria for estimating the cost of a cleaner exhaust
system. When they band together for better health care, they still
believe — mistakenly — that they are unqualified to decide what ought
to be done for their bowels and kidneys and blindly entrust themselves
to the doctor for almost any repair. Cross-cultural comparison of
practices provides no guide. Prescriptions for vitamins are seven times
more common in Britain than in Sweden, gamma globulin medication eight
times more common in Sweden than in Britain. American doctors operate,
on the average, twice as often as Britons; French surgeons amputate
almost up to the neck. Median hospital stays vary not with the
affliction but with the physician: for peptic ulcers, from six to
twenty-six days; for myocardial infarction, from ten to thirty days.
The average length of stay in a French hospital is twice that in the
United States. Appendectomies are performed and deaths from
appendicitis are diagnosed three times more frequently in Germany than
anywhere else.
Titmuss has summed up the difficulty of cost-benefit accounting in
medicine, especially at a time when medical care is losing the
characteristics it used to possess when it consisted almost wholly in
the personal doctor-patient relationship. Medical care is uncertain and
unpredictable; many consumers do not desire it, do not know they need
it, and cannot know in advance what it will cost them. They cannot
learn from experience. They must rely on the supplier to tell them if
they have been well served, and they cannot return the service to the
seller or have it repaired. Medical services are not advertised as are
other goods, and the producer discourages comparison. Once he has
purchased, a consumer cannot change his mind in mid-treatment. By
defining what constitutes illness the medical producer has the power to
select his consumers and to market some products that will be forced on
the consumer, if need be, by the intervention of the police: the
producers can even sell forcible internment for the disabled and
asylums for the mentally retarded. Malpractice suits have mitigated the
layman's sense of impotence on several of these points, but basically,
they have reinforced the patient's determination to insist on treatment
that is considered adequate by informed medical opinion. What further
complicates matters is that there is no “normal” consumer of medical
services. Nobody knows how much health care will be worth to him in
terms of money or pain. In addition, nobody knows if the most
advantageous form of health care is obtained from medical producers,
from a travel agent, or by renouncing work on the night shift. The
family that forgoes a car to move into a Manhattan apartment can
foresee how the substitution of rent for gas will affect their
available time; but the person who, upon the diagnosis of cancer,
chooses an operation over a binge in the Bahamas does not know what
effect his choice will have on his remaining time of grace. The
economics of health is a curious discipline, somewhat reminiscent of
the theology of indulgences which flourished before Luther. You can
count what the friars collect, you can look at the temples they build,
you can take part in the liturgies they indulge in, but you can only
guess what the traffic in remission from purgatory does to the soul
after death. Models developed to account for the willingness of
taxpayers to foot rising medical bills constitute similar scholastic
guesswork about the new world-spanning church of medicine. To give an
example: it is possible to view health as durable capital stock used to
produce an output called “healthy time.” Individuals inherit an initial
stock, which can be increased by investment in health capitalization
through the acquisition of medical care, or through good diet and
housing. “Healthy time”is an article in demand for two reasons. As a
consumer commodity, it directly enters into the individual's utility
function; people usually would rather be healthy than sick. It also
enters the market as an investment commodity. In this function,
“healthy time” determines the amount of time an individual can spend on
work and on play, on earning and on recreation. The individual's
“healthy time” can thus be viewed as a decisive indicator of his value
to the community as a producer.
Orientation on policy and theories on the dollar value of “health”
production divide the adherents of squabbling academic factions much as
realism and nominalism divided medieval divines. But to the point that
concerns the consumer, they just state in a roundabout way what every
Mexican bricklayer knows: only on those days when he is healthy enough
to work can he bring beans and tortillas to his children and have a
tequila with his friends. The belief in a causal relationship between
doctor's bills and health — which would otherwise be called modernized
superstition — is a basic technical assumption for the medical
economist.
Different systems have been used to legitimize the economic value of
the specific activities in which physicians engage. Socialist nations
assume the financing of all care and leave it to the medical profession
to define what is needed, how it must be done, who may do it, what it
should cost, and who shall get it. More brazenly than elsewhere,
input/output calculations of such investments in human capital seem to
determine Russian allocations. Most welfare states intervene with laws
and incentives in the organization of their health-care markets,
although only the United States has launched a national legislative
program under which committees of producers determine what outputs
offered on the “free market” the state shall approve as “good care.” In
late 1973 President Nixon signed Public Law 92-603 establishing
mandatory cost and quality controls (by Professional Standard Review
Organizations) for Medicaid and Medicare, the tax-supported sector of
the health- care industry, which since 1970 has been second in size
only to the military- industrial complex. Harsh financial sanctions
threaten physicians who refuse to open their files to government
inspectors searching for evidence of over-utilization of hospitals,
fraud, or deficient treatment. The law requires the medical profession
to establish guidelines for the diagnosis and treatment of a long list
of injuries, illnesses, and health conditions, mandating the world's
most costly program for the medicalization of health, production
through legislated consumer protection. The new law guarantees the
standard set by industry for the commodity. It does not ask if its
delivery is positively or negatively related to the health of people.
Attempts to exercise rational political control over the production of
medical health care have consistently failed. The reason lies in the
nature of the product now called “medicine,” a package made up of
chemicals, apparatus, buildings, and specialists, and delivered to the
client. The purveyor rather than his clients or political boss
determines the size of the package. The patient is reduced to an object
— his body — being repaired; he is no longer a subject being helped to
heal. If he is allowed to participate in the repair process, he acts as
the lowest apprentice in a hierarchy of repairmen. Often he is not even
trusted to take a pill without the supervision of a nurse.
The argument that institutional health care (remedial or preventive)
ceases after a certain point to correlate with any further “gains” in
health can be misused for transforming clients hooked on doctors into
clients of some other service hegemony: nursing homes, social workers
vocational counselors, schools. What started out as a defense of
consumers against inadequate medical service, will, first, provide the
medical profession with assurance of continued demand and then with the
power to delegate some of these services to other industrial branches:
to the producers of foods, mattresses, vacations, or training. Consumer
protection thus turns quickly into a crusade to transform independent
people into clients at all cost.
Unless it disabuses the client of his urge to demand and take more
services, consumer protection only reinforces the collusion between
giver and taker, and can play only a tactical and a transitory role in
any political movement aimed at the health-oriented limitation of
medicine. Consumer-protection movements can translate information about
medical ineffectiveness now buried in medical journals into the
language of politics, but they can make substantive contributions only
if they develop into defense leagues for civil liberties and move
beyond the control of quality and cost into the defense of untutored
freedom to take or leave the goods. Any kind of dependence soon turns
into an obstacle to autonomous mutual care, coping, adapting, and
healing, and what is worse, into a device by which people are stopped
from transforming the conditions at work and at home that make them
sick. Control over the production side of the medical complex can work
towards better health only if it leads to at least a very sizable
reduction of its total output, rather than simply to technical
improvements in the wares that are offered.
Equal Access to Torts
The most common and obvious political issue related to health is based
on the charge that access to medical care is inequitable, that it
favors the rich over the poor, the influential over the powerless.
While the level of medical services rendered to the members of
technical elites does not vary significantly from one country to
another, say from Sweden and Czechoslovakia to Indonesia and Senegal,
the value of the services rendered to the typical citizen in different
countries varies by factors exceeding the proportion of one to one
thousand. In many poor countries, the few are socially predetermined to
get much more than the majority, not so much because they are rich as
because they are children of soldiers or bureaucrats or because they
live close to the one large hospital. In rich countries members of
different minorities are underprivileged, not because, in terms of
money per capita, they necessarily get less than their share, but
because they get substantially less than they have been trained to
need. The slum dweller cannot reach the doctor when he needs him, and
what is worse, the old, if they are poor and locked in a “home,” cannot
get away from him. For these and similar reasons, political parties
convert the desire for health into demands for equal access to medical
facilities. They usually do not question the goods the medical system
produces but insist that their constituents have a right to all that is
produced for the privileged.
In the poor countries, the poor majorities clearly have less access to
medical services than the rich: the services available to the few
consume most of the health budget and deprive the majority of services
of any kind. In all of Latin America, except Cuba, only one child in
forty from the poorest fifth of the population finishes the five years
of compulsory schooling; a similar proportion of the poor can expect
hospital treatment if they become seriously ill. In Venezuela, one day
in a hospital costs ten times the average daily income; in Bolivia,
about forty times the average daily income. Everywhere in Latin
America, the rich constitute the 3 percent of the population who are
college graduates, labor leaders, political party officials, and
members of families who have access to services either through money or
simply through connections. These few receive costly treatment, often
from the doctors of their choice. Most of the physicians, who come from
the same social class as their patients, were trained to international
standards on government grants.
Notwithstanding unequal access to hospital care, the availability of
medical service does not inevitably correlate with personal income. In
Mexico about 3 percent of the population has access to the Institute de
Seguridad y Servicios Sociales de las Trabajadores del Estado (ISSSTE),
that special part of the social security system which still holds a
record for combining personal nursing care with advanced technological
sophistication. This fortunate group is made up of government employees
who receive truly equal treatment, whether they are ministers or office
boys, and can count on high-quality care because they are part of a
demonstration model. The newspapers, accordingly, inform the
schoolmaster in a remote village that Mexican surgery is as well
endowed as its counterpart in Chicago and that the surgeons who operate
on him measure up to the standards of their colleagues in Houston. When
high-level officials are hospitalized, they may be annoyed because for
the first time in their lives they have to share a hospital room with a
workman, but they are also proud of the high level of socialist
commitment their nation shows in providing the same for boss and
custodian. Both kinds of patient tend to overlook the fact that they
are equally privileged exploiters. Providing the 3 percent with beds,
equipment, administration, and technical care takes one-third of the
public-health-care budget of the entire country. To be able to afford
to give all of the poor equal access to medicine of uniform quality in
poor countries, most of the present training and activity of the health
professions would have to be discontinued. However, delivery of
effective basic health services for the entire population is cheap
enough to be bought for everyone, provided no one could get more,
regardless of the social, economic, medical, or personal reasons
advanced for special treatment. If priority were given to equity in
poor countries and service limited to the basics of effective medicine,
entire populations would be encouraged to share in the demedicalization
of modern health care and to develop the skills and confidence for
self-care, thus protecting their countries from social iatrogenic
disease.
In the rich countries, the economics of health are somewhat different.
At first sight, concern for the poor appears to demand further
increases in the total health budget. Yet the more people come to
depend on care by service institutions, the more difficult it is to
identify equity with equal access and equal benefits. Is equity
realized when equal numbers of dollars are available for the education
of rich and poor? Or does it require that the poor get the same
“education” although more will have to be spent on their account to
achieve equal results? Or must the educational system, in order to be
equitable, assure that the poor are not humiliated and hurt more than
the rich with whom they compete on the academic ladder? Or is equity in
learning opportunities provided only when all citizens share the same
kind of learning environment? This battle of equity versus equality in
the access to institutional care, already being waged in education, is
now shaping up in the medical field. In contrast to education, however,
the issue in health can easily be resolved on available evidence. The
per capita expenditure on health care, even for the poorest sector
within the United States population, indicates that the base line at
which such care turns iatrogenic has long since been passed. In rich
countries, the total budget of services for the poor, if used for that
which reinforces self-care, is more than ample. More access, even
though restricted to those who now receive less, would only equalize
the delivery of professional illusions and torts.
There are two aspects to health: freedom and rights. Above all, health
designates the range of autonomy within which a person exercises
control over his own biological states and over the conditions of his
immediate environment. In this sense, health is identical with the
degree of lived freedom. Primarily the law ought to guarantee the
equitable distribution of health as freedom, which, in turn, depends on
environmental conditions that only organized political efforts can
achieve. Beyond a certain level of intensity, health care, however
equitably distributed, will smother health-as-freedom. In this
fundamental sense, health care is a matter of well-ordered liberty.
Implicit in this concept is a preferred position of inalienable
freedoms to do certain things, and here civil liberty must be
distinguished from civil rights. The liberty to act without restraint
from government has a wider scope than the civil rights the state may
enact to guarantee that people will have equal powers to obtain certain
goods or services.
Civil liberties ordinarily do not force others to carry out my wishes;
a person may publish his or her opinion freely as far as the government
is concerned, but this does not imply a duty for any one newspaper to
print that opinion. A person may need to drink wine in his kind of
worship, but no mosque has to welcome him to do so within its walls. At
the same time, the state as a guarantor of liberties can enact laws
that protect equal rights without which its members would not enjoy
their freedoms. Such rights give meaning to equality, while liberties
give shape to freedom. One sure way to extinguish freedom to speak, to
learn, or to heal is to delimit them by transmogrifying civil rights
into civic duties. The freedoms of the self-taught will be abridged in
an overeducated society just as the freedom to health care can be
smothered by overmedicalization. Any sector of the economy can be so
expanded that for the sake of more costly levels of equality, freedoms
are extinguished.
We are concerned here with movements that try to remedy the effects of
socially iatrogenic medicine through political and legal control of the
management, allocation, and organization of medical activities. Insofar
as medicine is a public utility, however, no reform can be effective
unless it gives priority to two sets of limits. The first relates to
the volume of institutional treatment any individual can claim: no
person is to receive services so extensive that his treatment deprives
others of an opportunity for considerably less costly care per capita
if, in their judgment (and not just in the opinion of an expert), they
make a request of comparable urgency for the same public resources.
Conversely, no services are to be forcibly imposed on an individual
against his will: no man, without his consent, shall be seized,
imprisoned, hospitalized, treated, or otherwise molested in the name of
health. The second set of limits relates to the medical enterprise as a
whole. Here the idea of health-as-freedom has to restrict the total
output of health services within subiatrogenic limits that maximize the
synergy of autonomous and heteronomous modes of health production. In
democratic societies, such limitations are probably unachievable
without guarantees of equity — without equal access. In that sense, the
politics of equity is probably an essential element of an effective
program for health. Conversely, if concern with equity is not linked to
constraints on total production, and if it is not used as a
countervailing force to the expansion of institutional medical care, it
will be futile.
Public Controls over the Professional Mafia
A third category of political remedies for unhealthy medicine focuses
directly on how doctors do their work. Like consumer advocacy and
legislation of access, this attempt to impose lay control on the
medical organization has inevitable health- denying effects when it is
changed from an ad hoc tactic into a general strategy.
Four and a half million men and women in two hundred occupations are
employed in the production and delivery of medically approved health
services in the United States. (Only 8 percent are physicians, whose
net income after deductions for rent, personnel, and supplies
represents 15 percent of total health expenditures and whose average
income in 1973 was $50,000.) The total does not include osteopaths,
chiropractors, and others who might have specialized university
training and require a license to practice, but who, unlike
pharmacists, optometrists, laboratory technicians, and similar
physicians' underlings, do not produce health care of the same
prestige. Even further removed from the establishment, and therefore
excluded from these statistics, are thousands of purveyors of
nonconventional health care, ranging from mail-order herbalists and
masseurs to teachers of yoga.
Of the many claimants to competence who are more or less integrated
into the official establishment, about thirty categories are licensed
in the United States. In no state of the union is a license required
for fewer than fourteen kinds of practitioners. These licenses are
issued on completion of formal educational programs and sometimes on
the evidence of a successful examination; in rare instances,
proficiency or experience is a prerequisite for admission to
independent practice. Competent or successful work is nowhere a
condition for continuing in practice. Renewal is automatic, usually
upon payment of a fee; only fifteen out of fifty states permit a
physician's license to be challenged on grounds of incompetence. While
claims to specialist standing come and go on the fringes, the
specialties recognized by the American Medical Association have
steadily increased, doubling in the last fifteen years: half the
practicing American physicians are specialists in one of sixty
categories, and the proportion is expected to increase to 55 percent
before 1980. Within each of these fields a fiefdom has developed with
specialized nurses, technicians, journals, congresses, and sometimes
organized groups of patients pressing for more public funds. The cost
of coordinating the treatment of the same patient by several
specialists grows exponentially with each added competence, as does the
risk of mistakes and the probability of damage due to the unexpected
combination of different therapies. As the number of patient
relationships outgrows the elements in the total population, the
occupations dealing with medical information, insurance, and patient
defense multiply unchecked. Of course, physicians lord it over these
fiefs and determine what work these pseudo- professions shall do. But
with the recognition of some autonomy many of these specialized groups
of medical pages, ushers, footmen, and squires have also gained some
power to evaluate how well they do their own work. By gaining the right
to self-evaluation according to special criteria that fit its own view
of reality, each new specialty generates for society at large a new
impediment to evaluating what its work actually contributes to the
health of patients. Organized medicine has practically ceased to be the
art of healing the curable, and consoling the hopeless has turned into
a grotesque priesthood concerned with salvation and has become a law
unto itself. The policies that promise the public some control over the
medical endeavor tend to overlook the fact that to achieve their
purpose they must control a church, not an industry.
Dozens of concrete strategies are now being discussed and proposed to
make the health industry more health-serving and less self-serving:
decentralization of delivery; universal public insurance; group
practice by specialists; health- maintenance programs rather than
sick-care; payment of a fixed amount per patient per year (capitation)
rather than fee-for-service; elimination of present restrictions on the
use of health manpower; more rational organization and utilization of
the hospital system; replacement of the licensing of individuals by the
licensing of institutions held to performance standards; and the
organization of patient cooperatives to balance or support a
professional medical power.
Each of these proposals would indeed improve medical efficiency, but at
the cost of a further decline in society's effective health care. To
increase efficiency by upward mobility of personnel and downward
assignment of responsibility could not but tighten the integration of
the medical-care industry and with it social polarization.
As the training of middle-level professionals becomes more
expensive, nursing personnel in the lower ranks is becoming scarce.
Poor salaries, growing disdain for servant and housekeeping roles, an
increase in chronic patients (and consequent growing tedium in their
care), disappearance of the religious motivation for nuns and deacons,
and new opportunities for women in other fields all contribute to a
manpower crisis. In England nearly two-thirds of all low-level hospital
personnel come from overseas, usually from former colonies; in Germany,
from Turkey and Yugoslavia; in France, from North Africa; in the United
States, from racial minorities. The creation of new ranks, titles,
curricula, roles, and specialties at the bottom level is a doubtfully
effective remedy. The hospital only reflects the labor economy of a
high-technology society: transnational specialization on the top,
bureaucracies in the middle, and at the bottom, a new subproletariat
made up of migrants and the professionalized client.76
The multiplication of paraprofessional specialists further decreases
what the diagnostician does for the person who seeks his help, while
the multiplication of generalist auxiliaries tends to reduce what
uncertified people may do for each other or for themselves.
Institutional licensing would indeed permit a more efficient deployment
of personnel, a more rational health-manpower mix, and greater
opportunity for advancement: it would no doubt greatly improve the
delivery of medical staples such as dental work, bonesetting, and the
delivery of babies. But if it became the model for over-all health
care, it would be equivalent to the creation of a medical Ma Bell. Lay
control over an expanding medical technocracy is not unlike the
professionalization of the patient: both enhance medical power and
increase its nocebo effect. As long as the public bows to the
professional monopoly in assigning the sick-role, it cannot control
hidden health hierarchies that multiply patients. The medical clergy
can be controlled only if the law is used to restrict and disestablish
its monopoly on deciding what constitutes disease, who is sick, and
what ought to be done to him or her.
Misdirection of blame for iatrogenesis is the most serious political
obstacle to public control over health care. To turn doctor-baiting
into radical chic would be the surest way to defuse any political
crisis fueled by the new health consciousness. If physicians were to
become conspicuous scapegoats, the gullible patient would be relieved
from blame for his therapeutic greed. School-baiting did save the
institutional enterprise when crisis last hit in education. The same
strategy could now save the medical system and keep it essentially as
it is.
Quite suddenly in the 1970s the schools lost their status as sacred
cows. Driven by Sputnik, racial conflict, and new frontiers, the school
bubble had outgrown all nonmilitary budgets and had burst. For a short
while, the hidden curriculum of the school system lay exposed. It
became conventional wisdom that after a certain point in its expansion,
the school system inevitably reproduces a meritocratic class society
and neatly arranges people according to levels of highly specialized
torpor for which they are trained in graded, age-specific, competitive,
and compulsory rituals. Frustration of an expensive dream had led many
people to grasp that no amount of compulsory learning could equitably
prepare the young for industrial hierarchies, and that all effective
preparation of children for an inhuman socio-economic system
constituted systematic aggression against their persons. At this
point a new vision of reality could have grown into a radical revolt
against a capital-intensive system of production and the beliefs that
bolster it. But instead of blaming the hubris of pedagogues, the public
conceded to pedagogues more power to do precisely as they pleased.
Disgruntled teachers focused criticism on their peers, the methods, the
organization of schooling, and the financing of institutions, all of
which were defined as obstacles to effective education.
School-baiting enabled liberal schoolmasters to mutate into a new breed
of adult educators. School-baiting not only saved but — momentarily —
upgraded the salary and prestige of the teacher. Whereas before the
crisis point the schoolmaster had been restricted in his pedagogical
aggression to an age-specific group below sixteen years of age, which
was exposed to him during class hours in the school building to be
initiated into a limited number of subjects, the new knowledge-merchant
now considers the world his classroom. While the curricular teacher
could disqualify only those nonstudents who dared to learn a curricular
matter on their own, the new manager of lifelong and recurrent
“education,” “conscientization,” “sensitivity training,” or
“politicization” presumes to degrade in the eyes of the public any
behavioral patterns that he has not approved. The school-baiting of the
sixties could easily set the pattern for the coming medical war.
Following the lead of the teachers who declare that the world is their
classroom, some chic crusading physicians now jump onto the bandwagon
of medicine-baiting and channel public frustration and anger at
curative medicine into a call for a new elite of scientific guardians
who would control the world as their ward.
The Scientific Organization—of Life
Belief in medicine as an applied science generates a fourth kind of
countermeasure to iatrogenesis which inevitably increases the
irresponsible power of the health profession — and thereby the damage
medicine does. The proponents of higher scientific standards in medical
research and social organization argue that pathogenic medicine is due
to the overwhelming number of bad doctors let loose on society. Fewer
decision-makers, more carefully screened, better trained, more tightly
supervised by their peers, and more effectively in command over what is
done for whom and how, would ensure that the powerful resources now
available to medical scientists would be applied for the benefit of the
people. Such idolatry of science overlooks the fact that research
conducted as if medicine were an ordinary science, diagnosis conducted
as if patients were specific cases and not autonomous persons, and
therapy conducted by hygienic engineers are the three approaches which
coalesce into the present endemic health-denial.
As a science, medicine lies on a borderline. Scientific method provides
for experiments conducted on models. Medicine, however, experiments not
on models but on the subjects themselves. But medicine tells us as much
about the meaningful performance of healing, suffering, and dying as
chemical analysis tells us about the aesthetic value of pottery.
In the pursuit of applied science the medical profession has
largely ceased to strive towards the goals of an association of
artisans who use tradition, experience, learning, and intuition, and
has come to play a role reserved to ministers of religion, using
scientific principles as its theology and technologists as
acolytes. As an enterprise, medicine is now concerned less with
the empirical art of healing the curable and much more with the
rational approach to the salvation of mankind from attack by illness,
from the shackles of impairment, and even from the necessity of death.
By turning from art to science, the body of physicians has lost the
traits of a guild of craftsmen applying rules established to guide the
masters of a practical art for the benefit of actual sick persons. It
has become an orthodox apparatus of bureaucratic administrators who
apply scientific principles and methods to whole categories of medical
cases. In other words, the clinic has turned into a laboratory. By
claiming predictable outcomes without considering the human performance
of the healing person and his integration in his own social group, the
modern physician has assumed the traditional posture of the quack.
As a member of the medical profession the individual physician is an
inextricable part of a scientific team. Experiment is the method of
science, and the records he keeps — if he likes it or not — are part of
the data for a scientific enterprise. Each treatment is one more
repetition of an experiment with a statistically known probability of
success. As in any operation that constitutes a genuine application of
science, failure is said to be due to some sort of ignorance:
insufficient knowledge of the laws that apply in the particular
experimental situation, a lack of personal competence in the
application of method and principles on the part of the experimenter,
or else his inability to control that elusive variable which is the
patient himself. Obviously, the better the patient can be controlled,
the more predictable will be the outcome in this kind of medical
endeavor. And the more predictable the outcome on a population basis,
the more effective will the organization appear to be. The technocrats
of medicine tend to promote the interests of science rather than the
needs of society. The practitioners corporately constitute a research
bureaucracy. Their primary responsibility is to science in the abstract
or, in a nebulous way, to their profession. Their personal
responsibility for the particular client has been resorbed into a vague
sense of power extending over all tasks and clients of all colleagues.
Medical science applied by medical scientists provides the correct
treatment, regardless of whether it results in a cure, or death sets
in, or there is no reaction on the part of the patient. It is
legitimized by statistical tables, which predict all three outcomes
with a certain frequency. The individual physician in a concrete case
may still remember that he owes nature and the patient as much
gratitude as the patient owes him if he has been successful in the use
of his art. But only a high level of tolerance for cognitive dissonance
will allow him to carry on in the divergent roles of healer and
scientist.
The proposals that seek to counter iatrogenesis by eliminating the last
vestiges of empiricism from the encounter between the patient and the
medical system are latter-day crusaders of an inquisitorial kind. They
use the religion of scientism to devalue political judgment. While
operational verification in the laboratory is the measure of science,
the contest of adversaries appealing to a jury that applies past
experience to a present issue, as this issue is experienced by actual
persons, constitutes the measure of politics. By denying public
recognition to entities that cannot be measured by science, the call
for pure, orthodox, confirmed medical practice shields this practice
from all political evaluation.
The religious preference given to scientific language over the language
of the layman is one of the major bulwarks of professional privilege.
The imposition of this specialized language upon political discourse
about medicine easily voids it of effectiveness.
The deprofessionalization of medicine does not imply the proscription
of technical language any more than it calls for the exclusion of
genuine competence, nor does it oppose public scrutiny and exposure of
malpractice. But it does imply a bias against the mystification of the
public, against the mutual accreditation of self-appointed healers,
against the public support of a medical guild and of its institutions,
and against the legal discrimination by, and on behalf of, people whom
individuals or communities choose and appoint as their healers. The
deprofessionalization of medicine does not mean denial of public funds
for curative purposes, but it does mean a bias against the disbursement
of any such funds under the prescription or control of guild members.
It does not mean the abolition of modern medicine. It means that no
professional shall have the power to lavish on any one of his patients
a package of curative resources larger than that which any other could
claim for his own. Finally, it does not mean disregard for the special
needs that people manifest at special moments in their lives: when they
are born, break a leg, become crippled, or face death. The proposal
that doctors not be licensed by an in-group does not mean that their
services shall not be evaluated, but rather that this evaluation can be
done more effectively by informed clients than by their own peers.
Refusal of direct funding to the more costly technical devices of
medical magic does not mean that the state shall not protect individual
people against exploitation by ministers of medical cults; it means
only that tax funds shall not be used to establish any such rituals.
Deprofessionalization of medicine means the unmasking of the myth
according to which technical progress demands the solution of human
problems by the application of scientific principles, the myth of
benefit through an increase in the specialization of labor, through
multiplication of arcane manipulations, and the myth that increasing
dependence of people on the right of access to impersonal institutions
is better than trust in one another.
Engineering for a Plastic Womb
So far I have dealt with four categories of criticism directed at the
institutional structure of the medical-industrial complex. Each gives
rise to a specific kind of political demand, and all of them become
reinforcements for the dependence of people on medical bureaucracies
because they deal with health care as a form of therapeutic planning
and engineering. They indicate strategies for surgical, chemical, and
behavioral intervention in the lives of sick people or people
threatened with sickness. A fifth category of criticism rejects these
objectives. Without relinquishing the view of medicine as an
engineering endeavor, these critics assert that medical strategies fail
because they concentrate too much effort on sickness and too little on
changing the environment that makes people sick.
Most research on alternatives to clinical intervention is directed
towards program engineering for the professional systems of man's
social, psychological, and physical environment. “Non-health-service
health determinants” are largely concerned with planned intervention in
the milieu. Therapeutic engineers shift the thrust of their
interventions from the potential or actual patient towards the larger
system of which he is imagined to be a part. Instead of manipulating
the sick, they redesign the environment to ensure a healthier
population.
Health care as environmental hygienic engineering works within
categories different from those of the clinical scientist. Its focus is
survival rather than health in its opposition to disease; the impact of
stress on populations and individuals rather than the performance of
specific persons; the relationship of a niche in the cosmos to the
human species with which it has evolved rather than the relationship
between the aims of actual people and their ability to achieve them.
In general, people are more the product of their environment than of
their genetic endowment. This environment is being rapidly distorted by
industrialization. Although man has so far shown an extraordinary
capacity for adaptation, he has survived with very high levels of
sublethal breakdown. Dubos fears that mankind will be able to adapt to
the stresses of the second industrial revolution and overpopulation
just as it survived famines, plagues, and wars in the past. He speaks
of this kind of survival with fear because adaptability, which is an
asset for survival, is also a heavy handicap: the most common causes of
disease are exacting adaptive demands. The health-care system, without
any concern for the feelings of people and for their health, simply
concentrates on the engineering of systems that minimize breakdowns.
Two foreseeable and sinister consequences of a shift from
patient-oriented to milieu-oriented medicine are the loss of the sense
of boundaries between distinct categories of deviance, and a new
legitimacy for total treatment. Medical care, industrial safety, health
education, and psychic reconditioning are all different names for the
human engineering needed to fit populations into engineering systems.
As the health-delivery system continually fails to meet the demands
made upon it, conditions now classified as illness may soon develop
into aspects of criminal deviance and asocial behavior. The behavioral
therapy used on convicts in the United States and the Soviet Union's
incarceration of political adversaries in mental hospitals indicate the
direction in which the integration of therapeutic professions might
lead: an increased blurring of boundaries between therapies
administered with a medical, educational, or ideological rationale.
The time has come not only for public assessment of medicine but also
for public disenchantment with those monsters generated by the dream of
environmental engineering. If contemporary medicine aims at making it
unnecessary for people to feel or to heal, eco-medicine promises to
meet their alienated desire for a plastic womb.
8 – The Recovery of Health
Much suffering has been man-made. The history of man is one long
catalogue of enslavement and exploitation, usually told in the epics of
conquerors or sung in the elegies of their victims. War is at the heart
of this tale, war and the pillage, famine, and pestilence that came in
its wake. But it was not until modern times that the unwanted physical,
social, and psychological side-effects of so-called peaceful
enterprises began to compete with war in destructive power.
Man is the only animal whose evolution has been conditioned by
adaptation on more than one front. If he did not succumb to predators
and forces of nature, he had to cope with use and abuse by others of
his own kind. In his struggle with the elements and with his neighbor,
his character and culture were formed, his instincts withered, and his
territory was turned into a home.
Animals adapt through evolution in response to changes in their natural
environment. Only in man does challenge become conscious and the
response to difficult and threatening situations take the form of
rational action and of conscious habit. Man can design his relations to
nature and neighbor, and he is able to survive even when his enterprise
has partly failed. He is the animal that can endure trials with
patience and learn by understanding them. He is the sole being who can
and must resign himself to limits when he becomes aware of them. A
conscious response to painful sensations, to impairment, and to
eventual death is part of man's coping ability. The capacity for revolt
and for perseverance, for stubborn resistance and for resignation, are
integral parts of human life and health.
But nature and neighbor are only two of the three frontiers on which
man must cope. A third front where doom can threaten has always been
recognized. To remain viable, man must also survive the dreams which so
far myth has both shaped and controlled. Now society must develop
programs to cope with the irrational desires of its most gifted
members. To date, myth has fulfilled the function of setting limits to
the materialization of greedy, envious, murderous dreams. Myth assured
the common man of his safety on this third frontier if he kept within
its bounds. Myth guaranteed disaster to those few who tried to outwit
the gods. The common man perished from infirmity or from violence; only
the rebel against the human condition fell prey to Nemesis, the envy of
the gods.
Industrialized Nemesis
Prometheus was hero, not Everyman. Driven by radical greed (pleonexia), he trespassed beyond the limits of man (aitia and mesotes) and in unbounded presumption (hubris)
stole fire from heaven. He thus inevitably brought Nemesis on himself.
He was put into irons and chained to a Caucasian rock. An eagle preyed
all day on his liver, and heartlessly healing gods kept him alive by
regrafting his liver each night. Nemesis inflicted on him a kind of
pain meant for demigods, not for men. His hopeless and unending
suffering turned the hero into an immortal reminder of inescapable
cosmic retaliation.
The social nature of nemesis has now changed. With the
industrialization of desire and the engineering of corresponding ritual
responses, hubris has spread. Unbounded material progress has become
Everyman's goal. Industrial hubris has destroyed the mythical framework
of limits to irrational fantasies, has made technical answers to mad
dreams seem rational, and has turned the pursuit of destructive values
into a conspiracy between purveyor and client. Nemesis for the masses
is now the inescapable backlash of industrial progress. Modern nemesis
is the material monster born from the overarching industrial dream. It
has spread as far and as wide as universal schooling, mass
transportation, industrial wage labor, and the medicalization of health.
Inherited myths have ceased to provide limits for action. If the
species is to survive the loss of its traditional myths, it must learn
to cope rationally and politically with its envious, greedy, and lazy
dreams. Myth alone can do the job no more. Politically established
limits to industrial growth will have to take the place of mythological
boundaries. Political exploration and recognition of the necessary
material conditions for survival, equity, and effectiveness will have
to set limits to the industrial mode of production.
Nemesis has become structural and endemic. Increasingly, man-made
misery is the by-product of enterprises that were supposed to protect
ordinary people in their struggle with the inclemency of the
environment and against the wanton injustice inflicted on them by the
elite.
The main source of pain, of disability, and of death is now engineered,
albeit nonintentional, harassment. Our prevailing ailments,
helplessness, and injustice are largely the side-effects of strategies
for more and better education, better housing, a better diet, and
better health.
A society that values planned teaching above autonomous learning cannot
but teach man to keep his engineered place. A society that relies for
locomotion on managed transport must do the same. Beyond a certain
level, energy used for transportation immobilizes and enslaves the
majority of nameless passengers and provides advantages only for the
elite. No new fuel, technology, or public controls can keep the rising
mobilization and acceleration of society from producing rising
harriedness, programmed paralysis, and inequality. The same is true for
agriculture. Beyond a certain level of capital investment in the
growing and processing of food, malnutrition will become pervasive. The
results of the Green Revolution will then rack the livers of consumers
more thoroughly than Zeus's eagle. No biological engineering can
prevent undernourishment and food poisoning beyond this point. What is
happening in the sub-Saharan Sahel is only a dress rehearsal for
encroaching world famine. This is but the application of a general law:
When more than a certain proportion of value is produced by the
industrial mode, subsistence activities are paralyzed, equity declines,
and total satisfaction diminishes. It will not be the sporadic famine
that formerly came with drought and war, or the occasional food
shortage that could be remedied by good will and emergency shipments.
The coming hunger is a by-product of the inevitable concentration of
industrialized agriculture in rich countries and in the fertile regions
of poor countries. Paradoxically, the attempt to counter famine by
further increases in industrially efficient agriculture only widens the
scope of the catastrophe by depressing the use of marginal lands.
Famine will increase until the trend towards capital-intensive food
production by the poor for the rich has been replaced by a new kind of
labor-intensive, regional, rural autonomy. Beyond a certain level of
industrial hubris, nemesis must set in, because progress, like the
broom of the sorcerer's apprentice, can no longer be turned off.
Defenders of industrial progress are either blind or corrupt if they
pretend that they can calculate the price of progress. The torts
resulting from nemesis cannot be compensated, calculated, or
liquidated. The down-payment for industrial development might seem
reasonable, but the compound-interest installments on expanding
production now accrue in suffering beyond any measure or price. When
members of a society are regularly asked to pay an even higher price
for industrially defined necessities — in spite of evidence that they
are purchasing more suffering with each unit — Homo economicus, driven by the pursuit of marginal benefits, turns into Homo religiosus,
sacrificing himself to industrial ideology. At this point, social
behavior begins to resemble that of the drug addict. Expectations
become irrational and nightmarish. The self-inflicted portion of
suffering outweighs the damage done by nature and all the torts
inflicted by neighbors. Hubris motivates self-destructive mass
behavior. Classical nemesis was the punishment for the rash abuse of
privilege. Industrial nemesis is the retribution for dutiful
participation in the technical pursuit of dreams unchecked by
traditional mythology or rational self- restraint.
War and hunger, pestilence and natural catastrophes, torture and
madness remain man's companions, but they are now shaped into a new
Gestalt by the nemesis that overtakes them. The greater the economic
progress of any community, the greater the part played by industrial
nemesis in pain, impairment, discrimination, and death.
The more intense the reliance on techniques making for dependence, the
higher the rate of waste, degradation, and pathogenesis which must be
countered by yet other techniques and the larger the work force active
in the removal of garbage, in the management of waste, and in the
treatment of people made literally redundant by progress.
Reactions to impending disaster still take the form of better
educational curricula, more health-maintenance services, or more
efficient and less polluting energy transformers, and solutions are
still sought in better engineering of industrial systems. The syndrome
corresponding to nemesis is recognized, but its etiology is still
sought in bad engineering compounded by self-serving management,
whether under the control of Wall Street or of The Party. Nemesis is
not yet recognized as the materialization of a social answer to a
profoundly mistaken ideology, nor is it yet understood as a rampant
delusion fostered by the nontechnical, ritual structure of our major
industrial institutions. Just as Galileo's contemporaries refused to
look through the telescope at Jupiter's moons because they feared that
their geocentric world-view would be shaken, so our contemporaries
refuse to face nemesis because they feel incapable of putting the
autonomous rather than the industrial mode of production at the center
of their sociopolitical constructs.
From Inherited Myth to Respectful Procedure
Primitive people have always recognized the power of a symbolic
dimension; they have seen themselves as threatened by the tremendous,
the awesome, the uncanny. This dimension set boundaries not only to the
power of the king and the magician, but also to that of the artisan and
the technician. Malinowski claims that only industrial society has
allowed the use of available tools to their utmost efficiency; in all
other societies, recognizing sacred limits to the use of sword and of
plow was a necessary foundation for ethics. Now, after several
generations of licentious technology, the finiteness of nature intrudes
again upon our consciousness. The limits of the universe are subject to
operational probings. Yet at this moment of crisis it would be foolish
to found the limits of human actions on some substantive ecological
ideology which would modernize the mythic sacredness of nature. The
engineering of an eco-religion would be a caricature of traditional
hubris. Only a widespread agreement on the procedures through which the
autonomy of postindustrial man can be equitably guaranteed will lead to
the recognition of the necessary limits to human action.
Common to all ethics is the assumption that the human act is performed
within the human condition. Since the various ethical systems assumed,
tacitly or explicitly, that this human condition was more or less
given, once and for all, the range of human action was narrowly
circumscribed.
In our industrialized epoch, however, not only the object but also the
very nature of human action is new. Instead of facing gods we confront
the blind forces of nature, and instead of facing the dynamic limits of
a universe we have now come to know, we act as if these limits did not
translate into critical thresholds for human action. Traditionally the
categorical imperative could circumscribe and validate action as being
truly human. Directly enjoining limits to one's actions, it demanded
respect for the equal freedom of others. The loss of a normative “human
condition“ introduces a newness not only into the human act but also
into the human attitude towards the framework in which a person acts.
If this action is to remain human after the framework has been deprived
of its sacred character, it needs a recognized ethical foundation
within a new imperative. This imperative can be summed up only as
follows: “Act so that the effect of your action is compatible with the
permanence of genuine human life.” Very concretely applied, this could
mean: “Do not raise radiation levels unless you know that this action
will not be visited upon your grandchild.” Such an imperative obviously
cannot be formulated as long as “genuine human life” is considered an
infinitely elastic concept.
Is it possible, without restoring the category of the sacred, to attain
the ethics that alone would enable mankind to accept the rigorous
discipline of this new imperative? If not, rationalizations could be
created for any atrocity: “Why should background radiation not be
raised? Our grandchildren will get used to it!” In some instances, fear
might help preserve minimal sanity, but only when consequences were
fairly imminent. Breeder reactors might not be made operational for
fear that they would serve the Mafia for next year's extortions or
cause cancer before the operator died. But only the awe of the sacred,
with its unqualified veto, has so far proved independent of the
computations of mundane self-interest and the solace of uncertainty
about remote consequences. This could be reinvoked as an imperative
that genuine human life deserves respect both now and in the future.
This recourse to the sacred, however, has been blocked in our present
crisis. Recourse to faith provides an escape for those who believe, but
it cannot be the foundation for an ethical imperative, because faith is
either there or not there; if it is absent, the faithful cannot blame
the infidel. Recent history has shown that the taboos of traditional
cultures are irrelevant in combatting an overextension of industrial
production. The taboos were tied to the values of a particular society
and its mode of production, and it is precisely those that were
irrevocably lost in the process of industrialization.
It is not necessary, probably not feasible, and certainly not desirable
to base the limitation of industrial societies on a shared system of
substantive beliefs aiming at the common good and enforced by the power
of the police. It is possible to find the needed basis for ethical
human action without depending on the shared recognition of any
ecological dogmatism now in vogue. This alternative to a new ecological
religion or ideology is based on an agreement about basic values and on
procedural rules.
It can be demonstrated that beyond a certain point in the expansion of
industrial production in any major field of value, marginal utilities
cease to be equitably distributed and over-all effectiveness begins,
simultaneously, to decline. If the industrial mode of production
expands beyond a certain stage and continues to impinge on the
autonomous mode, increased personal suffering and social dissolution
set in. In the interim — between the point of optimal synergy between
industrial and autonomous production and the point of maximum tolerable
industrial hegemony — political and juridical procedures become
necessary to reverse industrial expansion. If these procedures are
conducted in a spirit of enlightened self-interest and a desire for
survival, and with equitable distribution of social outputs and
equitable access to social control, the outcome ought to be a
recognition of the carrying capacity of the environment and of the
optimal industrial complement to autonomous action needed for the
effective pursuit of personal goals. Political procedures oriented to
the value of survival in distributive and participatory equity are the
only possible rational answer to increasing total management in the
name of ecology.
The recovery of personal autonomy will thus be the result of political
action reinforcing an ethical awakening. People will want to limit
transportation because they want to move efficiently, freely, and with
equity; they will limit schooling because they want to share equally
the opportunity, time, and motivation to learn in rather than about the
world; people will limit medical therapies because they want to
conserve their opportunity and power to heal. They will recognize that
only the disciplined limitation of power can provide equitably shared
satisfaction.
The recovery of autonomous action will depend, not on new specific
goals people share, but on their use of legal and political procedures
that permit individuals and groups to resolve conflicts arising from
their pursuit of different goals. Better mobility will depend, not on
some new kind of transportation system, but on conditions that make
personal mobility under personal control more valuable. Better learning
opportunities will depend, not on more information about the world
better distributed, but on the limitation of capital-intensive
production for the sake of interesting working conditions. Better
health care will depend, not on some new therapeutic standard, but on
the level of willingness and competence to engage in self-care. The
recovery of this power depends on the recognition of our present
delusions.
The Right to Health
Increasing and irreparable damage accompanies present industrial
expansion in all sectors. In medicine this damage appears as
iatrogenesis. Iatrogenesis is clinical when pain, sickness, and death
result from medical care; it is social when health policies reinforce
an industrial organization that generates ill-health; it is cultural
and symbolic when medically sponsored behavior and delusions restrict
the vital autonomy of people by undermining their competence in growing
up, caring for each other, and aging, or when medical intervention
cripples personal responses to pain, disability, impairment, anguish,
and death.
Most of the remedies now proposed by the social engineers and
economists to reduce iatrogenesis include a further increase of medical
controls. These so-called remedies generate second-order iatrogenic
ills on each of the three critical levels: they render clinical,
social, and cultural iatrogenesis self-reinforcing.
The most profound iatrogenic effects of the medical technostructure are
a result of those nontechnical functions which support the increasing
institutionalization of values. The technical and the nontechnical
consequences of institutional medicine coalesce and generate a new kind
of suffering: anesthetized, impotent, and solitary survival in a world
turned into a hospital ward. Medical nemesis is the experience of
people who are largely deprived of any autonomous ability to cope with
nature, neighbors, and dreams, and who are technically maintained
within environmental, social, and symbolic systems. Medical nemesis
cannot be measured, but its experience can be shared. The intensity
with which it is experienced will depend on the independence, vitality,
and relatedness of each individual.
The perception of nemesis leads to a choice. Either the natural
boundaries of human endeavor are estimated, recognized, and translated
into politically determined limits, or compulsory survival in a planned
and engineered hell is accepted as the alternative to extinction. Until
recently the choice between the politics of voluntary poverty and the
hell of the systems engineer did not fit into the language of
scientists or politicians. Our increasing confrontation with medical
nemesis now lends new significance to the alternative: either society
must choose the same stringent limits on the kind of goods produced
within which all its members may find a guarantee for equal freedom, or
society must accept unprecedented hierarchical controls to provide for
each member what welfare bureaucracies diagnose as his or her needs.
In several nations the public is now ready for a review of its
health-care system. Although there is a serious danger that the
forthcoming debate will reinforce the present frustrating
medicalization of life, the debate could still become fruitful if
attention were focused on medical nemesis, if the recovery of personal
responsibility for health care were made the central issue, and if
limitations on professional monopolies were made the major goal of
legislation. Instead of limiting the resources of doctors and of the
institutions that employ them, such legislation would tax medical
technology and professional activity until those means that can be
handled by laymen were truly available to anyone wanting access to
them. Instead of multiplying the specialists who can grant any one of a
variety of sick- roles to people made ill by their work and their life,
the new legislation would guarantee the right of people to drop out and
to organize for a less destructive way of life in which they have more
control of their environment. Instead of restricting access to
addictive, dangerous, or useless drugs and procedures, such legislation
would shift the full burden of their responsible use onto the sick
person and his next of kin. Instead of submitting the physical and
mental integrity of citizens to more and more wardens, such legislation
would recognize each man's right to define his own health — subject
only to limitations imposed by respect for his neighbor's rights.
Instead of strengthening the licensing power of specialized peers and
government agencies, new legislation would give the public a voice in
the election of healers to tax-supported health jobs. Instead of
submitting their performance to professional review organizations, new
legislation would have them evaluated by the community they serve.
Health as a Virtue
Health designates a process of adaptation. It is not the result of
instinct, but of an autonomous yet culturally shaped reaction to
socially created reality. It designates the ability to adapt to
changing environments, to growing up and to aging, to healing when
damaged, to suffering, and to the peaceful expectation of death. Health
embraces the future as well, and therefore includes anguish and the
inner resources to live with it.
Health designates a process by which each person is responsible, but
only in part responsible to others. To be responsible may mean two
things. A man is responsible for what he has done, and responsible to
another person or group. Only when he feels subjectively responsible or
answerable to another person will the consequences of his failure be
not criticism, censure, or punishment but regret, remorse, and true
repentance. The consequent states of grief and distress are marks of
recovery and healing, and are phenomenologically something entirely
different from guilt feelings. Health is a task, and as such is not
comparable to the physiological balance of beasts. Success in this
personal task is in large part the result of the self-awareness,
self-discipline, and inner resources by which each person regulates his
own daily rhythm and actions, his diet, and his sexual activity.
Knowledge encompassing desirable activities, competent performance, the
commitment to enhance health in others — these are all learned from the
example of peers or elders. These personal activities are shaped and
conditioned by the culture in which the individual grows up: patterns
of work and leisure, of celebration and sleep, of production and
preparation of food and drink, of family relations and politics.
Long-tested health patterns that fit a geographic area and a certain
technical situation depend to a large extent on long-lasting political
autonomy. They depend on the spread of responsibility for healthy
habits and for the sociobiological environment. That is, they depend on
the dynamic stability of a culture.
The level of public health corresponds to the degree to which the means
and responsibility for coping with illness are distributed among the
total population. This ability to cope can be enhanced but never
replaced by medical intervention or by the hygienic characteristics of
the environment. That society which can reduce professional
intervention to the minimum will provide the best conditions for
health. The greater the potential for autonomous adaptation to self, to
others, and to the environment, the less management of adaptation will
be needed or tolerated.
A world of optimal and widespread health is obviously a world of
minimal and only occasional medical intervention. Healthy people are
those who live in healthy homes on a healthy diet in an environment
equally fit for birth, growth, work, healing, and dying; they are
sustained by a culture that enhances the conscious acceptance of limits
to population, of aging, of incomplete recovery and ever- imminent
death. Healthy people need minimal bureaucratic interference to mate,
give birth, share the human condition, and die.
Man's consciously lived fragility, individuality, and relatedness make
the experience of pain, of sickness, and of death an integral part of
his life. The ability to cope with this trio autonomously is
fundamental to his health. As he becomes dependent on the management of
his intimacy, he renounces his autonomy and his health must decline.
The true miracle of modern medicine is diabolical. It consists in
making not only individuals but whole populations survive on inhumanly
low levels of personal health. Medical nemesis is the negative feedback
of a social organization that set out to improve and equalize the
opportunity for each man to cope in autonomy and ended by destroying it.
|